субота, 12. децембар 2015.

The Critique of “Democracy in Europe” by Jurgen Habermas

With a good reason, Jurgen Habermas in his paper “Democracy in Europe” discusses the possible ways of reforming the institutional and social setup of the European Union. The main issue that he tackles is the one which has almost occupied the intellectual and public spheres in Europe and that is, democratic deficit of the EU. Habermas rightly indicates already in the introduction that “national democracies are becoming more and more entangled in problems arising out of growing discrepancy between a world society that is becoming increasingly interdependent at the systematic level and a world of states that remains fragmented”. This formulation, though, may be put in a slightly different form, which would again stress the inability of nation states to deal with contemporary world problems, but would at the same time define the problem in more social terms. So, one could argue that both international institutions and nation states, have become too weak to deal with socio – economic dynamics at the international level, same as with its repercussions at national levels. This means that both levels of institutional activities have become incapable of dealing with social reality in general. This formulation might sound similar to Habermasian one, but actually shifts the focus from the matter of formal sovereignty to the matter of social and economic structure, both internationally and nationally.

Habermas’ analysis of the international conditions that have accelerated the process of delegitimation of the EU on one hand and inability of nation states to tackle both socio – economic and political problems on the other, is convincing. He emphasizes two main problems: one is deepening of social and economic stratification internationally, which have led to political impotency of the nation states to deal with neoliberal offensive. The second issue is the EU’s lack of democratic legitimacy and therefore inability to provide nation states with a necessary back up support when facing problems on supra – national level. This is why Habermas calls for deepening of European political integration. The method he uses is also quite convenient.  While very easily “crashing” the argument of the non – existence of the “European demos” as being the main obstacle to the further and more democratic political integration of the EU, he agitates for further political integration of the Union on the basis of typical nation – building process. In brief, the argument is that no nation state has ever been created on the basis of preexisting demos, but rather as an imposed and produced legal constitution, from above. To put it in more simple terms, in spite of the fact that some inhabitants of Sicily or Catalonia don’t “feel” Italian or Spanish, this still doesn’t mean that nation building of Italy or Spain was unsuccessful. What is important, rather than a common identity of “homogeneous” demos, is common public sphere where people of a certain community, regardless of their identity claims, come together to discuss political issues and reach the main goal of every public sphere – the balance of interests. This is, apart from “double sovereignty”, European electoral law and balance of power among the existing EU institutions, Habermas’ main point – we need a common public sphere in order to create political unity, necessary for solving the issues concerning us at present time. This condition, as a matter of fact, is the main precondition for all other institutional and social reforms. Due to this reason, it is the European public sphere that I am going to address here, in order to challenge it.

My disagreement with Habermas therefore, starts and finishes at the point of spreading the public sphere onto European level. Even though pointing out that certain social groups transnationally suffer from economic crisis regardless of which nation state they live in (the same goes for the elites who do not suffer or even, benefit from the crisis regardless of their national belonging), Habermas somehow at the end, misses the point of why and how we should spread the arena of public debate from national to supranational level. In more simple terms, the problem isn’t that he finds this arena to be the mediator of different social interests across national boundaries, the mediator “between different conceptions of the common good”. The problem is rather that this public sphere, together with institutional changes, in his view, needs to be legally imposed from above. In other words, by avoiding and successfully “beating” the argument of “no further political integration without European demos”, he falls into another trap.

 It is true that nation states legally constituted civic solidarity from above, but the reasons and historical moment when this had been done is incomparable to the present moment and unsuitable to the problem which European Union and its member states are facing today. While nation states were established after the bourgeois revolution, in order to legitimize the new ruling class, while at the same time creating an additional legitimation tool called “public sphere”, they were still an emancipatory step away from feudalism. The new supra – national public sphere suggested by Habermas however, wouldn’t differ from its historical predecessors as long as it does not build itself upon a new, radically different initial point. Historical circumstances under which we live today are simply different from the ones at the time of the development of nation states that Habermas is referring to when trying to deal with present time’s problems. With that respect, what use to be emancipatory in one historical period (imposing the new legal framework from above), isn’t emancipatory in the other. It was evident already with the last wave of nation building processes (in Eastern Europe or former Yugoslavia especially, for instance), that “late” formations of nation states went into the opposite direction from the emancipatory road.

If this new Event from bellow would not take place, what we might got with reforms from the above (even if they aim at opening the new, wider and a common space for public discussion and mediating different interests), is what we always have gotten every time, when capitalism was in crisis. Here, I mainly refer to the “30 glorious years” and the welfare state model. It has been shown numerous times in history, that keeping the same basis, meaning the same social relations of production, while demanding better conditions of life for ever larger majority of people, always meant that the best you could get, are short terms concessions (more social giving and welfare), which only served as:

 1) An excuse not to change the basis radically, since even with this base social state is possible
2) As a perfect tool for bridging over the time of lack of legitimacy and wait for the new suitable moment for re-appropriation of intensity of class domination  

 Not so long after, it would be possible again to legitimize social spending cuts and cancelation of concessions that had previously been provided. As a matter of fact, Habermas himself says that the “idea of social Europe has perceptibly failed, with the reasons for the failure residing in Europe itself”. At the same time he argues that this doesn’t mean that resistance to the European unification is justifiable – and I indeed agree. However, neither “European unification” nor “European solidarity” necessarily have to be adopted or applied on the same basis upon which the EU was founded. On the contrary, isn’t his admission that causes of problems of ever larger social and economic discrepancies and identity conflicts in Europe are to be found in Europe itself, a good start for requisitioning the causes and not only effects of this European project? Isn’t this admission a perfect chance for admitting also that European economic problems are originating from the central pillar of European integration – which is the integration of European elites in order to secure a free flow of capital? Of course, when indicating (four) reasons of why we need to reform the EU today, Habermas mentions that initially, the intention was also to prevent the escalation of conflicts among European states. This is also correct. But, I would argue, more important issues from the very beginning were economic, rather than political ones. Here I am referring to the claim of Yanis  Varoufakis, that the EU was primarily established upon the agreement to remove the barriers for coal and steel  and that ECSC was nothing else but the outcome of the decision among six nations, to create the supra – national institutional set up for a (coal and steel) cartel, whose purpose was to regulate production and price levels.[1]  In accordance to that, it is logical that economic interests could not “trickle down” to the more serious political integration, since these interests would be threatened by the political democratization. As Jacques Ranciere points out, (from the standpoint of the elites), “there is only one good form of democracy – the one which confronts the catastrophe of democratic civilization”.[2]  This is why it is often heard in public debates that the only ones, who feel Europeans today, are the elites themselves.

Instead of concluding words, I would just refer to one of Habermas’ “super - structural” suggestions, namely the “double sovereignty”.  In order to have a double sovereignty, one first needs to have national sovereignty upon which to build the supra – national one. The problem is that national sovereignty have already been gone for a long time. Financial capitalism made politics in general dead, let alone concepts such as national sovereignty under the rule of multinational capital and international financial institutions. Doubling something which is non – existent would be as if we would be multiplying by zero. Of course, the solution is not the return to the concept of nation states. The solution is, as Habermas suggests, finding the tool for reaching the point of international solidarity. However this should be, in my view, achieved through establishing a different and less fragile grounds which would be posed from bellow. One may say that this sounds more utopian than changing the system radically from the inside – but creations are never to be judged in advance. The new creations are possible only to be imagined and then retroactively evaluated, when already created. There is no other way. Finally, Habermas argues that “higher level” or “shared” sovereignty means sacrificing part of national sovereignty in order to conserve the (old) revolutionary achievements in the past. The overall point of my paper lies in a counter – claim, which is in the “worst” case, as normative as Habermas’ claim. What we need today is, therefore, not conserving the old revolutionary achievements which are not any longer capable of dealing with contemporary political, economic and social problems, simply because they are the part of the problem. What we need today, are rather new revolutionary achievements.  
    

                                                                                               



[1] See: Varoufakis, Yanis, The Global Minotaur, Zed Books, 2013.75.
[2] See: Ranciere, Jacque, The Hatred of Democracy, Verso, 2014.10.

Нема коментара:

Постави коментар